There are two generic types of
statement of belief, a fact which leads quite naturally to the idea
that there must be two types of thing called belief; two things that
just happen to share the same name. Here are two examples:
a. "I really
believed that the Saddam regime had weapons capacity that posed an
immediate threat to the west and to Saddam's own people."
b. "I have an
abiding belief in the Christian God."
In both cases the speaker is the same:
former UK Prime Minister Tony Blair. Like many of us he is quite able
to make both kinds of statement of belief - often in the same
conversation - without feeling there to be any kind of conflict at
all between them. Statement (a), whether true or in fact a lie, is
logically quite plausible: it is possible for someone to believe that
a certain fact can be derived from a certain state of affairs.
Inductive reason, this statement suggests, had led him to conclude
that Saddam must be in possession of Weapons of Mass Destruction.
Statement (b) is quite different. It is quite absurd to think that it
is based on any process of reasoning from observation, that the
speaker has amassed appropriate cosmological evidence and derived
from it the theory that God indeed exists. In fact, it is only
fanatics who collapse these statements into the same thing, such as
the very earnest young men in London's Brick Lane who once informed
me that the Second Law of Thermodynamics proved Allah's existence.
They had full-colour books with diagrams to demonstrate as much.
Since the two are so different, why not
dispense altogether with this semantic space-sharing, freeing the two
concepts once and for all from their awkward joint tenancy to pursue
their separate housing destinies alone? After all, it would have been
quite possible for Tony Blair to say, "I really trusted the
evidence that..." or "I reasoned upwards from the evidence
before my eyes that..." or "Making what conclusions I could
from the meticulously assembled and arranged dossiers of my perhaps
over-zealous advisors I decided that..." These would have done
much the same job - their truth value, as I said, being a quite
separate matter from their internal logic. After all, isn't this
fusion of concepts we now quite happily distinguish between just a
formal-linguistic hangover from a more barbarous age when speakers
lacked the finesse of separating reason from belief?
Well, calling statements like statement
(a) something different, and no doubt less catchy, does nothing to
explain the status of statements like statement (b).
Transhistorically, I'd wager, belief in God has always meant
something different to the belief that the tiger will eat me if it
gets a chance or the belief that the frayed, sagging rope bridge will
collapse into the abyss below if I try to run across it. In fact, the
more you think about it the less statement (a) seems all that loftier
than the likes of statement (b) after all. Yet, it is of some kind of different order of statement. But there is no reason to assume it
inhabits some statelier realm of thought.
The transparent obviousness of their
difference is further muddied when we think about the many different
instances of statement type (a). Indeed we may want to introduce a
subdivision between those (call them a1) where we must directly
complete an act of induction and (a2) where the induction has already
been done for us. An example of (a2) might be when we, say, go to the
toilet and trust that gravity will draw our bodily expulsions
downwards instead of upwards. Then again, has anyone (outside of
space) ever doubted this result and had to puzzle out whether or not
to risk going for a wee? Does that make (a2) type statements closer
in fact to type (b) statements? Do they operate on blind faith and
casual assumption, on the individual surrendering her or his probing,
rational intellect to a dulled collective incuriosity? The
rejection of such acts of faith would put us in an absurd position,
like that of Sartre's protagonist Roquentin in his novel Nausea,
who rejects the complacency of
the citizens of Bouville on the grounds that they have not clearly
established for themselves - that is, assumed the full weight of
their responsibility to know - how a chair may not become a tongue or
a chestnut tree a giant phallus.
One
can question altogether the notion that type (a) statements are
inductive statements in the complete sense. Do they lead necessarily
to a general theory or are they always, at a certain point,
preliminary if not abortive? We did not arrive at a general theory of
gravity from understanding that rivers flowed from mountain source
towards the sea. And in fact, at most points, the observation would
have halted at precisely the point of particularity: this
river flows from its
source to the sea... or somewhere unknown. The thought of
generalising to all rivers would have come later, with the concept
'all rivers' and the concept 'world'. What's more, stopping short of
such generality may be a strength rather than a weakness of practical
thought.
How,
then, to grasp the similarity
between statement types (a) and (b) as more than merely
circumstantial? For an empiricist the answer might be that, since all
beliefs are reasoned from experience, God-belief and gravity-belief
statements are of the same kind. It is simply that gravity-belief
statements can be shown to be well-founded because they are based on
observations that come from within the realms of human experience.
But then aren't we guilty of doing the exact same thing as the
earnest young men in Brick Lane who believe that they can prove God's
existence with reference to physical laws? We turn the validity of statements of religious belief into a matter of evidence. Fine, you might think, let's relegate all belief to this status and simply dispose of religious belief - no great loss. Until you consider that neither observation nor custom are fit to evidence the universality of human rights or the rational principles of equality. Actually, Hume's analysis
is a good deal more sophisticated than this, since he argues that the
question of God's existence is simply debarred by human experience.
It is unanswerable - but also essentially uninteresting.
Yet
when somebody tells me that they believe in God or the Rights of Man I don't understand the statement the way I would if they told me they believed that the
evidence in the Oscar Pistorius case was convincing enough to convict
him of murder. What's interesting here is that only the latter
really requires a leap of faith - since, of the two, it is the only
one that makes a claim on any evidence. For quite bald statements of
facts - like the hair colour of the person in front of us; or our own
names when we are compos mentis - it would be odd to say, "I
believe that your hair is blonde" or "I believe that my
name is Hillary." The power of inductive reasoning is that its
provisional conclusions rely on attaining a degree of abstraction
that cannot be derived directly from the starting point. This is, of
course, the difference between deductive and inductive reasoning. The
statement about religion makes neither type of claim. Indeed, rather
than a leap of faith, statements of belief in God are performative.
They do what they say.
These statements enact
belief, reconfirming it in a similar if less painful way to
self-flagellation.
To
really get to grips with statements of religious
belief we have to at least know that they come embedded in a context.
In a syntactical sense, of course, there is no qualitative difference
between saying "I believe in the omnipotence of the Christian
God" and "I dance in the transparency of the beige Ether."
What makes the former meaningful for us (as opposed to simply grammatically correct) is not some process of
inductive reasoning but the symbolic
order that it
articulates and that we recognise through it. This is not down to
grammatical structure or to inductive reasoning but to the way language constructs the social
order in which our actions attain their meaning. This is what Jacques
Lacan called the order of the symbolic: a language-mediated world of
shared culture which we enter into when we construct meaningful
sentences. What belief in God and belief in the findings of some
ethnographical research have in common is neither the sharing of a
particular conception of belief, nor simply a syntactical
coincidence, but participation in a social process whereby meaning is
established through convention. The name given in Lacanian
psychoanalysis to the product of this process of establishing meaning
through negative differentiation (i.e. the "logic of the
signifier") is the symbolic order. Therefore, where both types
of belief-statement coincide is in their shared articulation of
different kinds of subjective commitment to
something beyond onself.
Sartre,
caught as he was between phenomenology and Marxism, is not very
fashionable today. Yet it may be worth returning to his view of
subjectivity in order to throw some light on the status of belief
statements like "I believe in the omnipotence of the Christian
God." Sartre took human consciousness as a starting point from
which he developed a dialectical theory of subjectivity. It was not
that he believed that language, the social world, and the "whole
human adventure" didn't precede the individual; it was simply
that an understanding of the "practical relations" between
"men" was only possible from the position of the
individual (a pan-social "perspective" was ruled out by the
very fact that the individual observer was mediated by that society).
Now, because Sartre felt that when new knowledge entered the universe
of the subject the subject itself was transformed, he argued that
"non-knowledge" itself played a key role in constituting
subjectivity. The partial-sightedness of the subjective position was
not simply a flaw, a limitation of vision, but was the characteristic
which allowed that subjectivity to make sense of the world. Thus, the limits of the subject appear as barriers in the real world.
Sartre gives the example of how partially-deprived eyesight is simply
compensated for by the extra work of the eye, with the field of
reality re-constituted through the eye's renewed efforts. The absence
of full vision is integrated by the subject as a new, different
totality, recognised as complete in-itself.
We need to ask ourselves, when assessing statements of belief, how
new knowledge is integrated into a subjective position, and what happens to the subjectivity through this process. This is the question that should be posed to those who believe
religious belief is "irrational": How do they propose to
"enlighten" the world? By simply shining the light of
reason upon it! What this ignores is one's own complex, subjective
entanglement with the world. It is rare indeed that religious
believers intend their professions of belief to contradict scientific
discovery; rather these kinds of belief-statement are living attempts
to resist the subjective integration of some new mode of control. "I
simply believe..." is a form of resistance, a means of deploying
the accumulated "practico-inert" - the old power of the
symbolic - against some new challenge. One might go further than the
atheist Sartre: the stakes in such arguments are not those between
"reason" and "unreason", but those of ideological
warfare. Not irrational leaps of faith, but reactionary deployment of
a power that at least discursively precedes the world of capitalist
modernity. As such "I believe..." has a profound
oppositional force. In fact, professions of belief in the values represented by the American constitution or flag are no different really than professions of belief in the truth of the Bible or the Koran. We should question what it is about the
contemporary conjuncture that not only summons forth such discursive
resistances but conjugates them with altogether more tormenting exactions on the perceived enemy.
No comments:
Post a Comment